• 兔儿爷

  • 主演:
  • 地区:
  • 年代: 1996

兔儿爷影评

140801570
  • 万里、阳光
    2021/11/2 23:12:19
    把它当叙事电影看还是可圈可点

    我先声明我不是水军。看多了电影都麻了。一开始在抖音看到最后一段,包贝尔这段戏,来了点兴趣,虽然剧情很老套,前期该说还要说,站在女主的观点这是¥@?!前面感情戏强行理顺那就这样吧,狗血剧情需要呗。后面半段讲真还是有点感觉的,于铁下跪要债,二条怕玉石俱焚也好良心发现也好给回了积蓄(面部表情丰富),后面是于铁回家被哥赶,乔杉收到发廊的飘带。这一对比,一下子就泪崩

    我先声明我不是水军。看多了电影都麻了。一开始在抖音看到最后一段,包贝尔这段戏,来了点兴趣,虽然剧情很老套,前期该说还要说,站在女主的观点这是¥@?!前面感情戏强行理顺那就这样吧,狗血剧情需要呗。后面半段讲真还是有点感觉的,于铁下跪要债,二条怕玉石俱焚也好良心发现也好给回了积蓄(面部表情丰富),后面是于铁回家被哥赶,乔杉收到发廊的飘带。这一对比,一下子就泪崩了。还有就是小侄女要钱买MP3吧(忘记是不是了),说于铁抠门,后面以刘德华的名义寄了过去。还有叮嘱铁爸的钙片没有记起来,反而记清楚儿子交代的事情(剧情需要)这也有点泪崩。后来的后来,佳丽结婚了并没有把于铁忘记带了它爱吃的串和青岛啤酒。这就够了,爱过!

    【详细】
    13969329
  • 乌鸦火堂
    2019/9/20 18:30:31
    “凤姐”别来无恙?专打各种直男!

    生猛+轻盈

    生猛+轻盈

    【详细】
    1051738
  • 水之南
    2012/2/11 4:40:44
    长短句
    一、多个时空


    《纯粹理性批判》中的第一经验类比(Analogies of Experience)要求在现象中有一个恒定且唯一之物来表象意识中的时间本身。恒定,或永恒,因为作为总体的时间本身是始终在那的;惟一,因为只有一个时间。这个惟一且永恒的东西,即现象中的实体(Substance)。康德明确把这个实体与洛克的托子(Substratum)区分开来,认为实体是以各种方式显现于人
    一、多个时空


    《纯粹理性批判》中的第一经验类比(Analogies of Experience)要求在现象中有一个恒定且唯一之物来表象意识中的时间本身。恒定,或永恒,因为作为总体的时间本身是始终在那的;惟一,因为只有一个时间。这个惟一且永恒的东西,即现象中的实体(Substance)。康德明确把这个实体与洛克的托子(Substratum)区分开来,认为实体是以各种方式显现于人的,而不是像托子那样不可知,也不显现。

    我要说,洛克的托子的作用是保证物的个体化与同一性。这个作用在康德那儿,似乎是由物自体和先验范畴共同完成。先验范畴组织现象,在使意识对现象的认识成为可能的同时,也使同一的意识本身成为可能——对先验对象的构成即对自我的构成。而物自体在这个过程中究竟如何起作用,不详。康德的物自体与洛克的托子一样,是个让理论显得尴尬,却又不得不进行的假设。

    尽管康德反复说现象中的实体不是洛克的托子,但这个实体究竟是什么,他又语焉不详。出于他对牛顿力学的接受,有人尝试将其理解为牛顿意义上的质量。我论证过,这样的解读将面临一个两难困境:如果实体是个体化了的质量,时间便不是惟一的;如果实体是现象世界中的总质量,基于二律背反的理由——这个总体无法成为经验对象——我们便无法经验到它。(详细论述见篇末附录)

    若是跳出康德阐释,取前一个困境:时间不是惟一的,每个作为现象的物都意味着一个独立的时间体系,我们就科幻了:空间中的一个一个的物,奠基着意识中的一个又一个时间系,我们可以生活在不同的时空中,当我们经验不同的物。甚至,对应地说,我们总在成为另一个人,当我们来到不同的时空。

    于是,我情愿把亨利的生活看作对康德的一次失败却有趣的解读。与其说他是一位时间旅行者,一位不停地穿越时空的超人或可怜人,不如说,他的意识中并没有一个绝对惟一的时间,他所来到并离开的每一个时空,都是一个独立自在的世界,尽管这些世界看上去很像,但哪个都不依赖于另一个——从理念的意义上说。


    二、沉默,或消失


    影片的前半部分,亨利的突然消失被解释为一种不治的遗传疾病。没有理由地,他时不时就去了另一个时空,赤身裸体地寻找可以穿上的衣服。仿佛常人来到一个新的环境,总是迫不及待地寻找一个身份,穿到自己身上。
    亨利总会在一个无从预料的时刻消失,克莱尔生活在一个不确定的世界中。她的爱情是确定的,但她爱的人不确定地存在着。她的生活中弥漫着不确定性,而这恰好让她格外珍惜亨利在她身边的每一分钟。

    克莱尔一次次怀孕又一次次流产,因为胎儿也有穿越症,莫名其妙地,便在某个时刻,出离了子宫。但克莱尔最后一次怀孕时,对亨利说,你每次消失都是因为感觉到了压力。所以,从现在开始,我要保持绝对地平静,这样胎儿就可以顺利出生了。
    看到这里,我恍然大悟,原来亨利的穿越症是个隐喻,关于男人的隐喻:面对压力,便会沉默与回避,这不正是男人的本能反应么——而这在女人看来,仿佛爱人去了另一个时空,不知何时才能回来,甚至,会不会回来。

    我查了查,电影改编自一位女造型艺术家的首部小说,写于一段失败的恋情之后。原来如此。

    很多年前听到过一个说法:爱情,对男人来说,是挂在墙上的一幅画,你并不总是去看它;但对女人来说,则是房间里音乐,你想不听都不行。所以,男人需要时不时地呆在纯然属于自我的世界里,在沉默中成为自己。女人却要认为这是对她的疏远、对亲密的疏离,并因此而坐立不安,想方设法闯进那份铁一般的沉默。结果,要么把自己撞疼,要么把爱情撞碎。
    这是对小儿女情态的描述。若成年点,便会更同情于另一个说法:人生在世,无非是男人讨慰藉,女人讨生活。人并不总是需要慰藉,尤其在得意之时。人却总在生活,就算你不想。


    三、看着,却无法改变


    在一次穿越中,亨利来到母亲身边,在地铁里,母亲在看报,他们作为陌生人简短却亲切的交谈了一会儿。亨利告诉母亲,他要结婚了,这个女孩让他感到安全。
    克莱尔问他:你什么不去阻止那场车祸,既然你可以回到车祸发生之前。“我无法阻止。无数次我回到过去,回到母亲还在的时候,但每次我都无法改变发生着的一切。”——这话让人特别难过。我们并不能改变过去,就像不能重新雕刻一座已然完成的塑像。

    不是么?很多时候,我们从自己当下的境遇中抽身而出,试图站在一个更开阔的角度,超脱地看现在的纠结、焦虑,或苦闷,并自嘲这些都没什么的。但当你身在当下,你知道未来的自己就坐在对面,笑着,看着自己,慈悲地。但你还是无法因此脱身而出。你仍然只能呆在你当下的处境中,无论是过分的快乐,还是仿佛无法挣脱的哀伤。

    每一个时刻都是三维的,它包含着过去、现在,和未来这三个维度。我们在回忆中编辑时间,编辑自己,有意无意地遗忘一些,并把另一些反复摩挲。过往明明灭灭,像晴天里,随风晃动的百叶窗投在墙上的影子。每次回忆之后,我们都成为另一个人。
    未来也是。未来无数次作为想象呈现于当下,各式各样地,仿佛清晰的回忆。回忆与憧憬,如同天平的两臂,对称着,平衡着,在现在这个支点上。所以,现在这个时刻,最重。


    四、期限


    有天聚会时,亨利中枪后痛苦挣扎的裸体突然出现在他们的门厅里。又消失了。克莱尔说,我从没见过四十岁之后的你。我见过的你总是很年轻。从这个时候起,死亡就成了他们中的另一个在场者,尽管它总是沉默着。

    亨利穿越到未来,遇见了自己的已经十岁的女儿。女儿告诉他,他死于自己五岁那年。她们一直很想念他。那时他们的女儿还没出生。那时克莱尔还一如既往地希望与亨利白头偕老,就像她还没长大时那样,就像她长大之后第一次遇到亨利时那样,就像亨利死后,她仍然留着亨利所有的衣服,等着亨利回来那样。

    于她而言,亨利是不会死的。他无非是走远了一下子回不来,他无非是在时空中迷了路,找不到一件让他温暖的衣服。

    女儿五岁那年,亨利和克莱尔都已知道,亨利即将死去,中弹而死。期限降至,可能在任何一天,任何一个时刻。在它到来之前,所有相聚的时光都是铭刻,都是用最日常的方式来进行的一次祭奠,一次追忆。当这个期限还不确定,他们相爱着,仿佛一对最平凡的恋人;当这个期限已然确定,他们相爱着,装作不知道他们即将分离。

    一个期限并不见得让期限到来之前的一切都显得美好。但,美好的东西都有一个期限。确定的期限,或不确定的期限。你不能试图挽留,那会犹如握紧手中的细沙,握得越紧,便流失得越快,宛如时间,从指缝间悄然流走。
    这个期限是否到来,何时到来,都不是你能选择的。你能做的,仅仅是在它到来之前的每一刻,不让自己在未来后悔——克莱尔明白这些,并且,她做到了。

    而,这不正是人生么。


    ——————
    附录:On Understanding Substance as Mass

    Introduction

    In the First Analogy of Experience, Kant argues that there must be some permanently persistent substance in the appearances which represents the persistence of time. Given Kant’s endorsement of Newtonian physics, commentators such as Eric Watkins suggest that such permanently persistent substance can be understood as Newtonian mass. In this paper, however, I argue that we face a dilemma when we try to cash out the notion of substance in terms of Newtonian mass.
    The paper proceeds in three steps. In the first section, I present the reason why there needs to be a permanently persistent substance in the appearances, and discuss why it seems to be compelling to conceive of the permanently persistent substance as Newtonian Mass. Then, in the second section, I argue that there are (only) two ways of conceiving of the permanently persistent substance as Newtonian mass, namely, to conceive of substance as individuated mass and to conceive of substance as the sum total of mass in the world of appearances. I show that there are textual indications as well as philosophical reasons to support each option. In the third section, however, I argue that both ways suffer from inescapable problems. Thus, conceiving of the permanently persistent substance in terms of Newtonian mass is not viable.

        
    Section I. The Permanently Persistent Substance

    In this section, I shall first present the reason why Kant thinks that there must be a permanently persistent substance in the appearances. I then discuss why it is compelling to conceive of such substance as Newtonian mass.
    In the chapter “System of all principles of pure understanding,” Kant discusses what makes possible the applications of the categories, i.e. the pure concepts of understanding, to objects, i.e. appearances that are given to sensible intuitions. That is, he discusses what it is that makes the categories have objective validity. Kant’s claim is that the applications of the categories are only possible under certain conditions, and these conditions are spelled out by the principles. For instance, the applications of the relational categories (substance-accidents, cause and effect, and mutual interactions) are possible if they are applied to objects according to the principles of Analogies of Experience. In addition to the three specific principles that correspond to each of the three relational categories, Kant also provides a general principle overarching all three Analogies. The general principle is stated in the second edition as follows: “Experience is possible only through the representations of a necessary connection of perceptions” (B 218). Watkins provides a helpful interpretation of this general principle:
    “The general idea is that each of the three relational categories represents a necessary connection that is required for experience of a single time and of objects existing and being temporally related to each other within a single time to be possible.” (My emphasis)
    Since this paper is focused on the notion of substance in the first Analogy, I shall ignore the second and third Analogies. So I now turn to a close examination of the first Analogy.
    The first Analogy, i.e. the principle of the persistence of substance, is stated in the second edition as follows: “In all change of appearances substance persists, and its quantum is neither increased nor diminished in nature.” (B 224) Watkins summarizes Kant’s argument for the first Analogy as follows (which I take to be a correct interpretation):
    Premise 1: Appearances, i.e. objects of experience, are made possible by time’s persistence.
    Premise 2: We do not perceive time itself.
    Therefore, In order to have experience of appearances, there must be some permanent substance in the appearances which can represent time or time’s persistence.
    While the appearances, as the objects given to our intuitions, are changing, the substance in appearances always stays the same and is permanent. So, Kant calls the permanent substance “the substratum of everything real” (B 225). But, some clarifications about Kant’s use of the term “substratum” are needed to prevent potential confusions. Substratum in Kant’s text does not mean what Locke uses this term to mean, namely, the bearer of properties which is unchanging and about which we can have no knowledge. For, according to Locke, we can only know what is given to our senses, but since the underlying substratum cannot be given to our senses, we have no access to it and therefore cannot know it.
    Kant, by constrast, does not think that there is any Lockean substratum in the world of appearances. For Kant, the fact that the states of the substance are changing and the substance stays the same does not mean the states are separable from the substance. Rather, the changing states of the substance are simply the ways in which the substance is given to us. Thus, we can know the substance, that is, we know the substance through its states. In order to avoid the Lockean implication of the term “substratum,” I shall only use “substance” to refer to the permanently persistent thing in the appearances despite Kant’s own use of “substratum” to talk about what is permanent in the appearances.
    Since I have argued that Kant’s notion of substance is not the Lockean substratum, then what is the Kantian notion of substance? We need a positive account of what the substance is. It is obvious that such a permanently persistent thing cannot be captured by ordinary physical objects, no matter whether they are natural objects (say, rocks) or artifacts (say, ships), for neither artifacts nor natural objects always stay the same such that in principle they can never suffer changes. So, it seems no ordinarily construed physical things can be qualified as substance that is permanently persistent. On the other hand, it is very hard to imagine that anything non-physical could play the role the substance is supposed to play. For it is hard to imagine how a non-physical being could be given to our sensible intuition or could be spatiotemporally organized by our a priori intuitions. So, it is unlikely that Kant means something non-physical by “substance.” Thus, there are two constraints on spelling out what substance is. First, it is something physical. Second, as I have shown, the physical being that can be understood as substance cannot be ordinarily individuated physical things such as planet or rock.
    In order to meet the above two conditions, Watkins suggests that, given Kant’s commitment to Newtonian science, it is likely that Kant has Newtonian mass in mind when he talks about the substance, since no matter how a physical object changes, its mass always stays the same. Since Newtonian mass is physical and is not an ordinarily individuated object, it seems quite compelling that the substance, which is permanently persistent, just is Newtonian mass. According to common sense, Newtonian mass is understood to be underlying objects such that we cannot directly perceive mass but can only perceive mass through the way it is given to our intuition, namely, through the perception of the objects that have mass. Thus, mass is neither unknowable nor directly perceivable, which seems to fit the description of the substance perfectly.
    Moreover, there are many textual indications that suggest the identification of substance with mass. Let me note two examples. First, recall the general principle overarching the three specific Analogies, namely, “In all change of appearances substance persists, and its quantum is neither increased nor diminished in nature.” (B 224) It seems that “quantum” is most naturally to be understood as mass, for mass seems to be the only thing in nature that is neither increased nor diminished on Newtonian physics.
    The other indication is Kant’s example to illustrate his claim that “he <a philosopher> thus assumed that as incontrovertible that even in fire the matter (substance) never disappears but rather only suffers an alteration in its form.” (B 288, my emphasis):
    “A philosopher was asked: How much does the smoke weigh? He replied: If you take away from the weight of the wood that was burnt the weight of the ashes that are left over, you will have the weight of the smoke.” (B 288)
    We can see that here Kant explicitly identifies substance with matter. And it is quite plausible to think that “matter” is just another way of saying “mass”. That is, “mass” seems to be the theoretical analog of the term “matter.” This hypothesis is supported by the example of the weight of smoke. For, in the example, the way to calculate the weight of smoke just is to calculate the mass (multiplies the gravitational constant).
    However, despite the compelling reasons for the identification of substance with mass, in the next sections, I shall argue that the substance cannot be understood as Newtonian mass, for when we try to work out the details of understanding the substance as mass, we face an unavoidable dilemma.


    Section II. Some Mass or the Sum Total of Mass

    In this section, I shall argue that there are two ways of conceiving of substance as Newtonian mass, and then show that both ways have some support from the text and are to some extent philosophically plausible. So, both ways deserve detailed considerations. But, in the next section, I shall argue that both ways face insurmountable problems.
    In identifying substance with mass, we need to settle an ambiguity: Is the mass meant to be some mass, say the mass of a rock which is 7 kilograms (a randomly chosen weight), or to be the sum total of mass in the world of appearances which is a very large but nonetheless definite amount? Since both some mass and the sum total of mass are permanently persistent, we cannot tell which way of identifying is more plausible with respect to the permanent persistence of substance. So, we must appeal to some other philosophically and/or textually interesting points to ground a preference in choosing one over the other.
    Let us first consider identifying the substance with some or individuated mass. First, the first Analogy is the principle according to which the relational category substance-accident is to be applied. Kant defines accidents to be “the determinations of a substance that are nothing other than particular ways for it to exist.”(B 229) Many commentators interpret the relation to be between object and its properties or states. Thus it makes more sense to think that the mass, which is the underlying bearer of properties, is the individuated mass of some object, instead of the sum total of mass in the world of appearances. For instance, in the example of the weight of smoke, Kant seems to conceive of substance as the matter, i.e. mass, of an individual object. Moreover, if we conceive of substance as the sum total of mass in the world of appearances, it is very hard to imagine how substance can be the bearer of properties or what kind of properties of which substance is the bearer.
    One might argue that, on the interpretation according to which substance is the sum total of mass, even though we could imagine no properties of which substance is the bearer, we can still conceive of substance as the bearer of (changing) states, i.e. the successive states of the world of appearances. I reply that Kant cannot accept such an idea because the states of the world are not objects of possible experience, for it is at least empirically true that no one could have the whole world of appearances as his object of experience. I will return to this point later on in the paper and use it to argue that conceiving of substance as the sum total of mass is untenable given Kant’s theoretic commitments.
    The above discussion is about reasons to prefer the identification of substance with some mass. I now turn to the reasons to prefer the identifications of substance with the sum total of mass. There are some textual evidences in the first Analogy that suggest this latter identification. For instance, the following passage:
    “…here the issue is only appearances in the field of experience, the unity of which would never be possible if we were to allow new things (as far as their substance is concerned) to arise. For then everything would disappear that alone can represent the unity of time, namely the identity of the substratum in which alone all change has its thoroughgoing unity. This persistence is therefore nothing more than the way in which we represent the existence of things (in appearances).” (B 229/A186, my emphasis)
    In this passage, Kant seems to identify the permanent persistent substance that represents the persistence of time with the unity of appearances, which seems to be the sum total of mass in the whole world of appearances. Let me argue for my understanding of this passage that it indicates that Kant identifies substance with the sum total of mass. I shall argue by reductio: Suppose Kant identified substance with individuated mass in the above passage. Then, it would make no sense to think that the arising of new substance could make the representation of the unity of time impossible. For the arising of new substance in no sense affects the substance, i.e. the mass, of the original objects. Let me use an example to illustrate. Suppose there is a rock whose mass is 7 kilograms and there arises a new object out of nothing, whose mass is 5 kilograms. Insofar as the rock’s mass remains the same, whether or not there are new masses arising out of nothing does not affect the unity of the rock’s mass, which is 7 kilograms. Therefore, in this passage, Kant conceives of substance as the sum total of mass in the whole world of appearances.
    So far I have shown that there are compelling reasons to identify substance with some mass or with the sum total of mass respectively. In the next section, I shall argue that there are also devastating reasons to each identification such that either way we go, we face unsolvable problems.


    Section III. One Single Time and the Limit of Possible Experience

    I now turn to the problems from which the each identification suffers. In this section, I shall argue that these problems make both identifications untenable. Let us first consider the identification of substance with individuated mass (i.e. some mass). I argue that the reason why individuated mass cannot be identified with substance is that individuated mass cannot represent the oneness of time. Recall Kant’s argument for the principle of the first Analogy: in order to have experiences of objects as temporal, we must identify a permanently persistent substance that can represent time in objects. While the states of the substance change, the substance persists so that the substance can represent time that persists. It is important to notice that time, which is supposed to be represented by substance in appearances, is one single time. But, individuated mass cannot represent one single time. For there are many individuated masses, for instance, the mass of a rock which is 7 kilograms, the mass of a cup which is 0.5 kilogram, and the mass of a table which is 3 kilograms, each of which is permanently persistent and undergoes changes. If one of them can represent time, any other also can. In that case, we do not have one single time. Rather, we have many times or time-series, each of which is persistent.
    Let me explain in details why multiply individuated masses cannot represent on single time. If these individuated masses can represent one single time, there must be some one single thing that is shared by these individuated masses that serves to represent the singularity of time. Whatever this shared thing is, it is not any of these individuated masses. Therefore, individuated mass cannot present one single time. However, on the other hand, time has be to singular. Here is a passage in the first Analogy which explains why time has to be one single time rather than a plurality of times:
    “Substances (in appearances) are the substrata of all time-determinations. The arising of some of them and the perishing of others would itself remove the sole condition of the empirical unity of time, and the appearances would then be related to two different times, in which existence flowed side by side, which is absurd. For there is only one time, in which all different times must not be placed simultaneously but only one after another.” (B 232/A189)
    One might argue that it does not matter how many individuated masses can represent time, it only matters that there is an individuated mass that represents time. Insofar as there is such a substance, which is permanently persistent, it suffices to represent one single time. I reply that, in that case, we still do not know which individuated mass is suppose to be the representer of the one single time in appearances. For there is not reason to think that the mass of one object is more suitable to represent time than the mass of another object is, insofar as both of the individuated masses are permanently persistent. Any choice of one over the other is arbitrary. But the unity or singularity of time is not arbitrary, for there can only be one time-series which persists, and any other time-series or temporal relations are just temporal parts of this unique time-series. Thus, I conclude that individuated mass cannot be the representer of time in appearances.
    I now turn to argue that the sum total of mass cannot represent time either. The idea of my argument is to make use of Kant’s solution to the Antinomies to show that the permanently persistent substance that represents time in the appearances cannot be the sum total of mass because the sum total of mass is not an object of possible experience. Let me lay out my argument in detail.
    In “The Antinomy of Pure Reason” chapter, Kant presents four pairs of arguments concerning four cosmological ideas about the world-whole, namely, whether there is a beginning of time, whether there is indivisibly simple substance, whether there is a first cause, and whether there is a necessary existent. As Allen W. Wood argues, the four antinomies share a general form, namely, the thesis of each antinomy claims that there must be a first member of the conditioning-conditioned chain, while the antithesis of each antinomy claims that there is no first member of such a chain and that the chain goes back into infinity. Kant argues that there are valid arguments for each of the four theses as well as valid arguments for each of the four antitheses, so we need a solution to such contradictions.
    Kant’s solution to the contradictions, as Wood argues, relies on his doctrine of transcendental idealism. As for the first two antinomies, Wood argues
    The mathematical antinomies are generated by mathematical principles that apply to things only insofar as they are given in sensible intuition…But these [the first two] series of conditions are never given to intuition as a whole...The theses are false because the principles of possible experience make it impossible for objects corresponding to the cosmological ideas of a first event, a largest extent of the world or a simple substance, ever to be given to intuition.”
    Thus, the reason why Kant thinks that the claims made by the theses of the first and second antinomies are false is that neither the beginning of time nor the spatial boundary of the world or an indivisible substance can ever be given to our sensible intuition. If something cannot be given to our sensible intuition, according to Kant, we cannot have experience of it. Let me call this principle the object-of-sensible-intuition principle, namely, if something cannot be given to our sensible intuitions, then it cannot be object of our possible experience. And we can apply this principle to an object to determine whether that object can be object of possible experience. That is, if the object in question can be given to our sensible intuition, then the object can be object of our possible experience, but if the object cannot be given to our sensible intuition, then it cannot be object of our possible experience.
    Now, let me apply the object-of-sensible-intuition principle to the idea of the sum total of mass. We can see that the sum total of mass cannot be given to our sensible intuition, so, the sum total of mass cannot be object of our possible experience. For the world of appearances seems to mean the whole universe or cosmos (because everything in the universe stands in causal relations to each other), there is no way for all of the mass in the whole universe to be given to our sensible intuition. Actually, we do not even know whether there are spatial boundaries of the universe, so we do not even know whether the sum total of mass in the all universe is finite. Thus, the sum total of mass cannot be object of possible experience. So, the sum total of mass cannot be that which represents time in appearances. For the reason there must be a permanently persistent substance in appearances which represents time is to make our temporally connected representations of objects possible. But, if the sum total of mass cannot be object of experience, it cannot make our experience of object possible. Thus, the permanently persistent substance in appearances cannot be the sum total of mass.
    One might object that in the antinomies, the cosmological ideas at issue are condition-condition series. (B 436/A410) But the sum total of mass is not a series. Rather, it is an aggregate about which the question of conditioning and conditioned does not arise at all. Thus, Kant’s remarks on the antinomies have no bearing on whether the idea of the sum total of mass has any objective validity or significance. Moreover, the first two antinomies concern whether the conditioning-conditioned series go on into infinities. And it seems that it is impossible for us to experience infinity, for no matter what we experience it is finite insofar as we have experienced it. But, the quantum of the sum total of mass seems to be a definite and finite amount. By virtues of what can we claim that the sum total of mass cannot be object of experience? Is this “cannot” an empirical cannot, or an In-Principle cannot? If the answer is the former, the empirical “cannot” does not seem to be strong enough to show that the sum total of mass cannot be experienced, because we cannot know or predict whether in the future empirical sciences and technologies will make the sum total of mass possible object of experience. If the answer is the latter, at least further explanations of why the sum total of mass, which is a finite and definite amount, cannot be object of possible experience in principle are needed.
    To the first objection I have two replies. First, in the first antinomy, Kant also discusses whether there is boundary or the largest extent of space. It is not obvious that there is a spatial series in the sense that it is obvious that there is a temporal series in which one moment succeeds its previous moments. However, according to Kant, we can think of the space acquiring its quantum through repeatedly or successively adding spatial units to the previous spatial units. (A 428/B 456) That is, the way of conceiving of space as a spatial series depends on the way of conceiving of time as a temporal series, which is naturally serial. Then, by the same token, we can also think of the sum total of mass acquiring its quantum by successively adding massive units to previous massive units. Thus, if the object-of-sensible-intuition principle applies to the idea of the boundary of space, it should also apply to the idea of the sum total of mass of the whole world of appearances.
    Second, the fact that Kant applies the object-of-sensible-intuition-principle to the first two (or three) cosmological ideas to solve the contradictions does not mean that the principle can only be employed to deal with the antinomies. If the principle is applicable to other ideas, we can also use the principle to deal with other ideas. Since the object-of-sensible-intuition principle is derived from transcendental idealism, which is an important element in the whole Critique, there is no reason why the principle cannot be applied to other ideas than cosmological ideas. Thus, it is legitimate to use the object-of-sensible-intuition principle to show that the sum total of mass of whole world of appearances cannot be object of possible experience. So, the sum total of mass cannot be what represents time in appearances.
    My reply to the second objection has two steps. First, it needs to be clarified that, although the first two antinomies concern whether the conditioning-conditioned series are infinite, Kant’s solution by the object-of-sensible-intuition principle does not rely on the whether the series are infinite. The principle only concerns whether the things to which the cosmological ideas refer can be given to our sensible intuition. It does not concern whether the things are infinite. It seems true that infinity cannot be object of sensible intuition. But this does not mean that all finite things can be given to our sensible intuition. Actually Kant rejects the claim that all finite things can be given to our sensible intuition. For Kant thinks the thesis of the first antinomy is false, because the beginning of time or the boundary of space cannot be given to our sensible intuition so that it cannot be object of possible experience.
    The second step of my reply is to spell out in which sense of “cannot,” the sum total of mass cannot be object of possible experience. It seems to me that the distinction between empirical “cannot” and In-Principle “cannot” is hard to cash out in the context of Critique. For, in the Critique, any legitimate claim to knowledge entails that the object of which the knowledge is can be experienced. Thus, it seems that the empiricality of the “cannot” entails the In-Principality of the “cannot”.
    However, concerning the claim that we cannot predict whether in the future empirical sciences and technologies will make the sum total of mass possible object of experience, what would Kant say? Would Kant agree that future sciences and technologies might or could transform a transcendent idea into an idea which refers to object of possible experience? I do not think he would. For Kant thinks his Critique settles metaphysical questions once and for all by theoretical reason, which is static or a-historical. Future discoveries made by sciences and technologies should be able to do no damage to the doctrines in Critique. Moreover, it should be odd to Kant’s ear that progresses made by empirical sciences could have any bearings on the doctrines in the Critique, which he builds up from scratch employing only pure reason, which is absolutely a-historical.
    Thus, I conclude that the above arguments show that identifying substance with the sum total of mass in the world of appearance is not tenable. Since I showed earlier in this section that identifying substance with individuated mass is not tenable either, I conclude that the general strategy of identifying substance with mass is untenable.


    Section IV. Concluding Remarks

    In this paper, I showed that a seemingly very promising way of understanding the permanently persistent substance discussed in the first Analogy, namely, conceiving of substance as Newtonian mass, is untenable. Then, I wonder whether there are other promising ways of providing a positive account of substance or actually it is the case that the notion of substance in the first Analogy is itself untenable. At this stage, maybe I could follow Kant’s stance on the things of themselves, namely, they exist, but we can have no knowledge about the way of their existence. But, at the same time, we need to have this minimal conviction that they exist. Similarly, concerning substance, we can have no knowledge about what the permanently persistent substance is, but we need to have the minimal conviction that it exists in the world of appearances and it serves to represent time.
    【详细】
    530131278
  • 匠青
    2022/10/19 17:33:19
    这些兄弟们,还是温柔了点

    人类身上有一个很棒的能力,叫做体会……再来说下这部作品,好不好呢?如果从剧情和逻辑上来分析,有很多瑕疵,无论是兄弟情义还是越狱行为,都过于戏剧化,尤其是在冲突场面中,脑回路清奇,甚至让人扼腕叹息……但是,我喜欢他们的认真。微笑也好,点头示意也罢,每个角色都有种坦率的豪气,可以让人心情爽朗,继而生出亲近……如果不能释义解惑,赶走暂时的忧愁也不错啊……

    人类身上有一个很棒的能力,叫做体会……再来说下这部作品,好不好呢?如果从剧情和逻辑上来分析,有很多瑕疵,无论是兄弟情义还是越狱行为,都过于戏剧化,尤其是在冲突场面中,脑回路清奇,甚至让人扼腕叹息……但是,我喜欢他们的认真。微笑也好,点头示意也罢,每个角色都有种坦率的豪气,可以让人心情爽朗,继而生出亲近……如果不能释义解惑,赶走暂时的忧愁也不错啊……

    【详细】
    14714182
  • 林安
    2022/2/18 20:06:42
    随便看看随手吐槽

    好多明星在啊,分镜拍摄不错做饭DJ放音乐这段,毫无理由mc演技一般,rap也一般这是讲北漂还是爱情?尚进的追梦逆袭故事?讲北漂,讲酒吧一分钟的朋友?经纪人卖房给赞助复活喊麦歌手,复活就能火吗帮上进复活,俩人吃火锅对经纪人发脾气,剧本不行啊20w整黑幕,上了比赛进决赛开始卖惨,“我说的没上进好”咔咔咔一顿煽情在这寻找彷徨失去,这不是歌词?决赛终于唱了rap,还是北京北京的歌词艾伦梦洁一直在回忆

    好多明星在啊,分镜拍摄不错做饭DJ放音乐这段,毫无理由mc演技一般,rap也一般这是讲北漂还是爱情?尚进的追梦逆袭故事?讲北漂,讲酒吧一分钟的朋友?经纪人卖房给赞助复活喊麦歌手,复活就能火吗帮上进复活,俩人吃火锅对经纪人发脾气,剧本不行啊20w整黑幕,上了比赛进决赛开始卖惨,“我说的没上进好”咔咔咔一顿煽情在这寻找彷徨失去,这不是歌词?决赛终于唱了rap,还是北京北京的歌词艾伦梦洁一直在回忆杀,好尴尬情侣吵架就去酒吧上班了?玩都地主斗气,酒吧比喝酒,设计不合理老板想灌女的,这么多整过好看的不要?分了还是没分,联系这么多得罪老板救女朋友,世界和平俩人喝到吐,第二天醒来默契早餐,发现女的有新对象了女的又来求复合比赛找好酒,理由不行

    “你没看她朋友圈吗”拉黑怎么看

    “别以因为误会,误了一辈子”

    “大宝贝”就是她爹,去机场追她,好俗

    然后继续配音剪辑回忆杀

    这段删除好友穿帮了,明明拉黑了,拉黑按钮没点上

    “回北京干什么,看你变成什么样子”追梦?然后后悔?被改变服务员陪着被甩宿醉女生,陪玩陪喝大冒险冰块砸老板,去车里暖和,吐槽人家整容,女的还洗白“一生看自己最多”然后就看见跑车高富帅男友看见男朋友出轨就离开北京,俩人一顿感慨,气泡音念台词 ,假文艺,加上回忆剪辑。情感传达的不深,还强行煽情

    【详细】
    14227591
  • notsobad
    2017/12/20 9:17:10
    窥见欧洲的衰落
    《夺金四贱客》德国片+名导演+当前德国中生代砥柱=隐隐想说什么却最终决定闭嘴的平庸之作。 喜欢笨贼一箩筐版纵横四海的观众会比较满意,但我不觉得本片的梗有什么德国特征 走出影院一个感觉就是德国(欧洲)当代文化的没落,他们面对太多的问题,但碍于政治正确却连讨论都讳莫...  (展开)
    《夺金四贱客》德国片+名导演+当前德国中生代砥柱=隐隐想说什么却最终决定闭嘴的平庸之作。 喜欢笨贼一箩筐版纵横四海的观众会比较满意,但我不觉得本片的梗有什么德国特征 走出影院一个感觉就是德国(欧洲)当代文化的没落,他们面对太多的问题,但碍于政治正确却连讨论都讳莫...  (展开)
    【详细】
    9000217
  • 白开水
    2018/3/26 13:30:05
    虎头蛇尾
    给它的第一评价就是虎头蛇尾吧,没有看过原漫画,但就电影来说,算不上好看,只能说是一部可以用来打发时间的电影。 一开始营造了十足的悬疑气氛,案件的设计也有《七宗罪》的影子,连环杀人犯以惩罚为主题完成自己所谓的艺术作品。这种艺术感的惩罚式杀人手段悬疑片并...  (展开)
    给它的第一评价就是虎头蛇尾吧,没有看过原漫画,但就电影来说,算不上好看,只能说是一部可以用来打发时间的电影。 一开始营造了十足的悬疑气氛,案件的设计也有《七宗罪》的影子,连环杀人犯以惩罚为主题完成自己所谓的艺术作品。这种艺术感的惩罚式杀人手段悬疑片并...  (展开)
    【详细】
    9250219
  • 静水流深
    2017/8/19 23:43:36
    剧本太差,神仙也救不了烂片的命

    剧本太差,莫名其妙。

    古天乐女儿的人设像个弱智,未成年性行为,还突然想生小孩,父亲当面逮捕其男友,这样的设置有何意义?难道一个正常的女儿在泰国失踪,她爸爸就不会去救了?

    剧本如果像韩国电影,揭露本国黑幕也行,算有社会意义。可是香港人胡编乱造,编排泰国黑幕,让人不齿。

    外籍雇佣兵大boss好像头脑有病,不想赚钱,只想和中国功夫决斗,让香港警察古天乐横扫工厂,

    剧本太差,莫名其妙。

    古天乐女儿的人设像个弱智,未成年性行为,还突然想生小孩,父亲当面逮捕其男友,这样的设置有何意义?难道一个正常的女儿在泰国失踪,她爸爸就不会去救了?

    剧本如果像韩国电影,揭露本国黑幕也行,算有社会意义。可是香港人胡编乱造,编排泰国黑幕,让人不齿。

    外籍雇佣兵大boss好像头脑有病,不想赚钱,只想和中国功夫决斗,让香港警察古天乐横扫工厂,香港警察的武力值也是无敌了。

    林家栋为何如此卖命,冒死违法帮市长换心,难到是好基友,从头到尾装酷的死脸,怎么发挥其演技?

    泰国的警察局长如此弱势,被市长的幕僚玩弄于鼓掌,竟然连警察局长的女儿都敢绑架?

    古天乐身负重伤,居然轻松进入市长府邸开枪杀人,太瞎编了。

    【详细】
    8762351
  • 娱乐码头
    2021/7/24 14:35:38
    反腐扫黑绝不手软,这尺度让人细思极恐

    娱乐码头/文

    近来,群像电影比较流行,先有张艺谋的《悬崖之上》,后有《阳光姐妹淘》,再加上献礼片《1921》、《革命者》,以及灾难抗疫医疗片《中国医生》,近期看到的电影都是以群像呈现的,然而8月6日全国上映的犯罪悬疑题材电影《危险记忆》,同样也是一部群像电影,汇集了丁海峰、甘

    娱乐码头/文

    近来,群像电影比较流行,先有张艺谋的《悬崖之上》,后有《阳光姐妹淘》,再加上献礼片《1921》、《革命者》,以及灾难抗疫医疗片《中国医生》,近期看到的电影都是以群像呈现的,然而8月6日全国上映的犯罪悬疑题材电影《危险记忆》,同样也是一部群像电影,汇集了丁海峰、甘婷婷、李滨、李东翰、乔乔、张亚坤、刘俐儿、周浩东、牛飘、张笑君、陈逸恒等老中青三代实力派演员,为我们呈现了一部尺度极大的犯罪悬疑大片。

    《危险记忆》改编自长篇小说《走向深渊的秘书》,讲述了副市长秘书袁行舟遭遇车祸导致失忆,刑警队长刘扬调查发现袁遭遇的其实是专门针对他的杀局。在袁行舟寻回记忆的过程中,频频陷入危险境地,多方势力开始蠢蠢欲动,并由此牵引出了一个惊天的秘密,迷局就此展开。影片比想象中好看,郭大群导演对节奏、画面、音乐的把握都很好,不拖拉、不磨蹭、几乎没有一句废话没有一个废镜头,有内涵、有思考、有意义,不得不说郭大群导演是非常非常用心的。

    无论电视荧屏还是电影银幕,反腐扫黑的影视作品数不胜数,从《人民的名义》到《巡回检察官》,从《风中有朵雨做的云》到《扫黑·决战》,再到《危险记忆》,这些影视作品都有一特点,就是尺度足够大,导演敢拍,演员敢演,gd敢上,观众就敢看!其中个人最喜欢娄烨的《风中有朵雨做的云》,摇晃的镜头里呈现的故事,真实的让人后怕,而《危险记忆》同样如此,尺度大的让人细思极恐,相比《风中有朵雨做的云》,给的很直接,黑社会、强拆、裸贷、谋杀、贪污、受贿……

    作为一部犯罪动作大片,它的完成度相当高,节奏明快、剪辑凌厉,并没有陷入空洞渲染悬疑气氛里面,而是在很多时候用高智商的犯罪来牵动观众的心,既不过分卖弄又不至于平淡无奇,张弛间都十分有度,在犯罪的探讨中进行了人性深处的审视。个人最喜欢李东翰饰演的袁行舟和周浩东饰演的副市长对峙那场戏,当袁行舟持枪冲进会场时,所有人都以为他会一枪解决了战斗,万万没想到他所做的一切都是自己计划的,为自己留好了后路,这也是他为什么要失忆的原因,当他主动带上手铐的时候,让我们看清了什么是人性。

    这部电影虽然没有太多血腥、恐怖的画面,但悬疑气氛营造得非常好,情节较为紧凑,层层推理,逻辑性较强,剧情很充实,反转再反转令人意外,枪战、动作戏也非常出彩。演员们演技全员在线,影片为他们注入了鲜活的生命力。饰演吴妍的甘婷婷,她是串联起几方线索的关键人物。李滨、李东翰、周浩东也很让人惊讶,尤其李滨演绎的刑警拿捏得非常准确,和杀手的几场动作戏非常精彩,特别是医院楼道里的打斗,动作拳拳到肉干净利索,让人看到他不一样的一面。

    反腐扫黑绝不手软,观看完全片,不得不说影片将悬疑与动作结合的还是相当完美的,紧迫感还是很强的,整体水平、观看体验都不错。还是很值得我们思考的,不失为一部好片。

    【详细】
    137041333
  • 铱璱
    2022/4/26 22:21:29
    化蝶只是传说,实际上她被困了一辈子

    本片最妙的设定是,徐老怪把梁山伯与祝英台相爱的故事背景改成梁山伯家里是没落士族,后来科考考上县令之后再去提亲。其用意就是在于强调祝英台和梁山伯抛去家族势力,两人有一样的起点,他们是一个世界的人,祝英台哪怕嫁给梁山伯也是不会为生活发愁的。

    徐老怪想讲的门第之差,抨击的是祝英台她爹娘朱门对朱门,竹门对竹门的虚伪,电影里祝英台的爹妈根本不是为了女儿的生计考虑反对这门亲事,而是想把他们的

    本片最妙的设定是,徐老怪把梁山伯与祝英台相爱的故事背景改成梁山伯家里是没落士族,后来科考考上县令之后再去提亲。其用意就是在于强调祝英台和梁山伯抛去家族势力,两人有一样的起点,他们是一个世界的人,祝英台哪怕嫁给梁山伯也是不会为生活发愁的。

    徐老怪想讲的门第之差,抨击的是祝英台她爹娘朱门对朱门,竹门对竹门的虚伪,电影里祝英台的爹妈根本不是为了女儿的生计考虑反对这门亲事,而是想把他们的女儿当联姻工具来巩固他们士族派系的权力,至于对面的人爱不爱祝英台,女儿过得会不会幸福他们根本不在乎。

    故事中胡人把他们打的赶过江了他们仍然在盘算着自己的乌纱帽,为了衬托出这种虚伪和无能的士族权力争斗,徐克甚至根本都不拍马文才这个角色,因为马文才是谁根本不重要,梁祝的悲剧在于这个他俩都想要抗争这虚伪的官场,都想要靠自己的才华和双手打造出一个自由的世界,这两人根本不是恋爱脑。

    梁山伯有着报国之志,他在上学的时候士族子弟全在摸鱼玩乐,只有他发着高烧还在点灯夜读,后面是靠自己当上县令才去提的亲,祝英台想要的也不是爱情,从电影一开始她娘问她如果前面的路走不通了怎么办?她把面前的阻挡物挪开继续往前走,她要的是不被当工具利用的人生,只要她爹为她的幸福稍微考虑一下,都不会把她心爱的人打得半死,更不会在她流出血泪之后仍然让下人把她抬进婚轿,生在这样的大门大户,谁能说不是可悲?

    她的爹娘都是大厦将倾下自欺欺人的蝼蚁罢了

    【详细】
    14361627
  • 喝酒的狐狸
    2021/12/18 12:34:32
    流浪与归宿—此心安处是吾乡
    这篇剧评可能有剧透 看完最后一集后,我长舒一口气,最开始怀着怀疑的心态来看这部续作,原本以为第一季是巅峰,但无论在叙事水平和内涵深度上,本作都毫无疑问超越了前作。 本作的故事线有两条,一条是现实中发生的事,另一条是旅人与蜂鸟的故事。两条线互相照应,关于旅人和蜂鸟在现实故事中的对...
    这篇剧评可能有剧透 看完最后一集后,我长舒一口气,最开始怀着怀疑的心态来看这部续作,原本以为第一季是巅峰,但无论在叙事水平和内涵深度上,本作都毫无疑问超越了前作。 本作的故事线有两条,一条是现实中发生的事,另一条是旅人与蜂鸟的故事。两条线互相照应,关于旅人和蜂鸟在现实故事中的对...  (展开)
    【详细】
    14074253
  • 高尔基的梯子
    2020/8/3 21:38:32
    野心太大,却连人物成长都看不到
    1.既视感特别严重,反派也很好猜,超英拯救世界已经套路化了。 2.设定还是有点意思,家族式的超英,对原生家庭也有很多描写,还有大背景的时空管理局,剧集的野心显的很大,两个时空特工刻画的很有反派魅力,贡献了最精彩的打戏,相爱相杀的部分几次反转拍的很好看,黑泽尔的感...  (展开)
    1.既视感特别严重,反派也很好猜,超英拯救世界已经套路化了。 2.设定还是有点意思,家族式的超英,对原生家庭也有很多描写,还有大背景的时空管理局,剧集的野心显的很大,两个时空特工刻画的很有反派魅力,贡献了最精彩的打戏,相爱相杀的部分几次反转拍的很好看,黑泽尔的感...  (展开)
    【详细】
    12773217
  • sitemap